Athenian Legacies: Essays on the Politics of Going On Together. By JOSIAH
OBER. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005. Pp. xiii + 273. Cloth,
$29.95. ISBN 0–691–12095–1.
Order this text for $13.57 from Amazon.com using this link and benefit
CAMWS and the Classical Journal:
http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/redirect-home/classjourn-20
Print Version (Projected): CJ 103.1: 101–3
Ober offers this collection of previously published essays as a “sequel” to
his Athenian Revolution (Princeton, 1996). Moving beyond the origins of the
Athenian democracy to discuss its maintenance, he examines how the
Athenians could “go on together” after devastating foreign invasions and
civil wars. For Ober, Athens was less homogenous than it is usually
depicted to be, and can therefore serve as a useful comparandum for modern
democratic theory. Although the essays are wide-ranging, he seeks
throughout to show how the Athenians managed the “centrifugal push towards
social diversity” and the “centripetal pull towards political coherence”
(p. 7) as he considers questions concerning the group and the individual,
theory and practice, continuity and change. Rather than regard the tensions
arising from the diversity-coherence conflict as a destructive force that
needed to be neutralized for the democracy to carry on, he suggests that
the Athenians channeled them in productive ways.
In Chapter Two, Ober criticizes the modern propensity to analyze the
Athenian democracy in terms of institutions with an emphasis on
constitutional history as distorting, and uses the Council of 500 as a test
case to show the advantages of a cultural approach. Arguing that Athenian
citizenship is best understood as a form of “social knowledge” that
promotes team-work (p. 33), he presents the council as a “master network”
(p. 37) that seamlessly integrates the center and periphery through a
combination of artificial and natural units (the tribe and the deme).
Although Athens was not a face-to-face community, the organization of the
council and the distribution of the demes within the tribes networked the
citizens so that there were only a few “degrees of separation” between any
two Athenians (p. 41). Next, Ober draws on Thucydides to show how the past
may be used as a positive moral lesson in a heterogeneous society to
establish moral authority. The social meaning of any historical event,
however, is at best ambiguous, and a community that is divided will
invariably ascribe divisive meanings to the past.
Chapters Four and Five respond to political theorists who advocate
cosmopolitanism and constitutional liberalism, respectively, over
democracy. In reply to the cosmopolitanists, Ober notes the dangers of
globalism and the benefits of the nation-state for the non-elite. The
constitutional liberalists, by contrast, separate liberalism from
democracy, arguing that liberalism does not depend on democracy, and that
democracy is desirable only to the extent it protects individual rights.
Given the ease with which rights can be legally restricted even within a
society with a well-defined constitution (as contemporary events have
shown), this trust in non-democratic governments to promote liberal values
is overly optimistic. To be sure, democracies do not always adhere to their
ideals, but non-democratic governments are even less likely to restrain
themselves.
Ober is less convincing in his efforts to show that the Athenian democracy
extended “quasi-rights” to non-citizens. In theory, the hubris law
protected slaves, but an Athenian was probably never prosecuted for (let
alone convicted of) hubris against a slave. While Pseudo-Xenophon
notoriously claims that slaves were protected from the attacks of
passers-by, it is also the case that one litigant accused his opponents of
having sent a young Athenian into his fields to pick flowers so that he
would attack the boy on the assumption that he was a slave and thus
inadvertently become guilty of hubris against a citizen (D. 53.16).
Needless to say, slaves were vulnerable daily to random violence at the
hands of their masters.
Chapter Six is a particularly valuable discussion of Athenian civic
education, which Ober sums up as a balancing act between “thinking alike”
and “thinking differently” (p. 129). On the one hand, the Athenians needed
to agree on a core set of co-operative values (freedom, equality and
security) promoted in public discourse through the daily business of their
political institutions. On the other hand, they avoided developing a formal
educational system so as not to stifle the expression of heterogeneous
viewpoints necessary for effective deliberation. In addition, Ober
persuasively argues for an implicit dialogue between the democracy and its
critics. Although elite criticism was restricted to the private arena
because of the democratic control of public discourse, it was indirectly
and partially responsible for political reforms and thus played a pivotal
role in strengthening the democracy.
In Chapter Seven, Ober shows how Socrates’ statement in the Apology that he
would not adhere to a hypothetical law that outlawed philosophizing does
not contradict his assertion in the Crito that he was obligated to obey the
laws. Since the hypothetical law would be in conflict with the pre-existing
law on impiety, Socrates had the legal responsibility to continue
philosophizing so as not to disobey the impiety law. The next two chapters
are more open-ended. Chapter Eight originated as a response paper in a
panel at the 2001 APA meeting using models from social science history and
culture history to explain the Amnesty of 403 BCE. Ober goes through the
strengths and weaknesses of each approach, but avoids siding with either
group. In Chapter Nine, he draws on speech-act theory to warn against
over-interpretation of Greek horoi.
In his final chapter, Ober explores the iconography of the Athenian
democracy, starting with the statues of the tyrannicides and ending with
the relief on the stele of the Eukrates nomos that shows the crowning of
Demos. Whereas the statues of Harmodius and Aristogeiton emphasize
action—transition from tyranny to democracy—the relief depicts democracy as
a “state of being” that can only be momentarily interrupted by tyranny (pp.
216–19, 223–5). Between the two stands the Dexileus relief, illustrating
the co-opting of democratic imagery for aristocratic display and the
tension between democratic and aristocratic values within Athenian civic
space (pp. 237–46).
In sum, these essays are impressive for their breadth and depth. Ober
focuses on key questions concerning unity and stasis while engaging in
political theory, and persuasively shows how ancient Athens offers a useful
comparison in modern attempts to reinvigorate democracy. He makes a
compelling case to explain how the Athenians were able to continue on not
in spite, but because of their differences.
ANDREW WOLPERT
University of Florida, Gainesville
You may remove yourself from the CJ-Online list-serve by sending an
email to: [log in to unmask]
Leave the subject line blank, and in the first line of the message
write: UNSUBSCRIBE cj-online
|