Alcman and the Cosmos of Sparta. By GLORIA FERRARI. Chicago: The University
of Chicago Press, 2008. Pp. viii + 184 + 20 color plates + 2 halftones.
Cloth, $45.00. ISBN 978–0–226–66867–3.
Order this text for $35.06 from Amazon.com using this link and benefit
CAMWS and the Classical Journal:
http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/redirect-home/classjourn-20
Previously published CJ Online reviews are at
http://classicaljournal.org/reviews.php
CJ Online 2009.07.05
Due to its fragmentary state, as well as our incomplete knowledge of
performance contexts in archaic Sparta, Alcman’s famed Louvre Partheneion
fragment has had a long and contested history of interpretation. Ferrari
(F.) provides a novel interpretation of the poem, while situating it within
its literary and cultural matrices. She states that the purpose of her book
is to show “that cosmic imagery … runs through Alcman’s song and
governs its staging” (p. 7) and that “on the occasion of a major state
festival celebrating the cycle of the seasons, the chorus dances the Hyades
and points to the Moon, Dawn, and Night” (p. 17). Although by no means
the first scholar to note astral imagery in the poem, F. is the first to do
so in such an extended fashion. The basic questions for all readers, then,
are: does F. persuade us that the cosmic imagery she purports to uncover is
as widespread as she claims? Are her interpretations overly constrictive?
In the introduction, F. criticizes the assumption that the poem preserves a
transcript of a performance in which the chorus speak of themselves as
themselves. She points out that lyric choruses “could, and did, play the
part of mythical or epic characters” (p. 11), and then asserts that
“the chorus of the Partheneion … take on the role of archetypal
dancers, in their case a chorus of stars” (p. 17). F. is correct, of
course, that we should be aware of our assumptions, and there is no reason
to assume prima facie that the chorus could not play something other than
themselves.
In Chapter 1, “The Myths,” F. systematically addresses the myths
presented in the poem and interprets them in light of their social and
literary context. She elegantly points out that the myth of Tyndareus,
Hippocoon and his sons shows the problems that ensue when an illegitimate
heir takes control of the state; at Sparta with its system of dual
kingship, this myth of fraternal rivalry and illegitimate succession would
have had important political resonance. F. then turns to the famed Aisa and
[Poros] passage of the papyrus and interprets Aisa as “the time allotted
to darkness and night” and Poros as “the road of heaven.”
Traditionally, Poros and Aisa (Portion and Allotment) are taken to refer to
the duration of life given the heroes mentioned in the immediately
preceding catalogue. The word geraitatoi, which is textually sure, works
well with this opinio communis. But, if we follow F.’s interpretation,
“the road of heaven” and “the time allotted to darkness and night”
are called the oldest [gods?]. This seems strange, even given the Greek
fondness for personification. F. also excises some now widely accepted
supplements, presumably because they do not work with her thesis. While
such excisions are legitimate, I would have liked to see her address the
surrounding text that is still sure.
In lines 16–17, F. finds reference to the myth of Phaethon, which she
connects with Poros and Aisa, discussed above as “path” and
“measure.” She suggests that “poros and aisa in the gnome are highly
relevant, since it was the youth’s inability to follow the ‘path’ of
the Sun and thus keep to the ‘measure’ of the day that resulted in
disaster.” Once again, I wish F. had discussed the broader extant text.
She omits reference to lines 18 and 19, in which the possibility that
females besides Aphrodite might be married is clearly mentioned, and
focuses only on one bride, Aphrodite, for Phaethon. In support of her
interpretation, F. offers the supplement “flee from” in line 17 (i.e.,
no one should flee from marrying Aphrodite), but Blass’ widely accepted
“try” seems preferable (i.e., let no one try to marry Aphrodite), since
the gnomic line 16 seems to exhort humans to be aware of their mere mortal
status. I doubt that many scholars will follow F. and read the myth of
Phaethon into this passage.
In Chapter 2, “The Chorus,” F. focuses on the chorus and its
performance. F. addresses the notoriously difficult line 49, but does not
consider the possibility that the passage is simply corrupt. Like G.O.
Hutchinson in his Greek Lyric Poetry, I would obelize the passage. Shortly
thereafter, F. asks whether we should assume that the females (Agido,
Hagesichora, Anesimbrota) mentioned in the poem are historical, and
(following others) points out that many of the women seem to have
“speaking names.” Is this fortuitous or do names like Hagesichora,
“leader of the chorus,” tell us that we are wrong to regard these as
historical personages rather than acted roles? Given her thesis, F.
stresses that these names do not refer to historical personages but can be
used of actors generically. This may be true, but, unfortunately for F.’s
thesis, the names do not connect in any obvious way with names for stars.
Moreover, F.’s argument that the poem would not be preserved, were these
historical characters, is particularly weak. For example, we still have
epinician odes in which Hieron of Syracuse plays a prominent role.
In her discussion of the hotly contested lines 60–3, F. points out that
the Pleiades and Hyades are often positioned in literature together in
reference to the beginning of winter, the time for plowing. Since the
Pleiades are mentioned in the text, F. deduces that Alcman’s chorus must
be the Hyades, who are competing against the Pleiades; this is all heavily
based on the hotly contested verb makhontai, “fight.” But the texts F.
marshals in support of her thesis (Hes. Op. 614–17; Il. 18.486) never
describe the Pleiades “fighting” with the Hyades; rather it seems that
the Pleiades and Hyades move in tandem. If we are to presume that
Alcman’s chorus of Hyades is fighting the Pleiades, as F. argues, we
should expect a similar arrangement within Greek discourse concerning the
Pleiades and the Hyades, but the comparanda F. offers suggest the opposite.
Alcman’s text is problematic for F.’s thesis in other ways as well. In
“we are carrying a plow/robe,” the language seems quite literal and
works better on the assumption that an offering is being made on behalf of
the chorus and civic body to a deity, presumably Orth(r)ia. In none of the
comparison texts F. cites is phero used to describe the introduction of the
plowing season. Moreover, an interpretation of the verb’s object as the
“plowing season” rather than the “plow” itself warrants more
explanation. Most commentators also take Orthriai as a dative singular—as
Hutchinson notes, the syntax practically demands it—while F. takes it as
a nominative plural with the Pleiades. The common interpretation, contra
F., works well if we assume that this poem was written for a festival at
which a deity was given some material offering, either a plow or a robe. It
may also be that we are wrong to even consider plow/plowing season as a
possibility for pharos here, since robes are fitting gifts for goddesses in
Greek cult and the interpretation of pharos as plow apparently cannot be
supported outside this text and the commentary on it; Hutchinson, for
example, takes it for granted that pharos must mean robe (pp. 77, 91). F.
further suggests that Agido is Dawn, Hagesichora the Moon, and Anesimbrota
Night; but she offers no substantial evidence in support of these
equivalences. For many reasons, therefore, I find myself unable to accept
the interpretation F. offers for interpreting Alcman’s chorus as the
Hyades.
Nor can I believe that the chorus refer to their performance as ponoi,
“labors,” at line 88. It seems odd to say that a goddess healed a
chorus from performing a ritual. More likely the chorus are calling upon
the goddess as a reliever of some specific toils/sufferings the community
experienced, and the text encourages this interpretation, since a reference
to peace comes shortly thereafter. As Hutchinson points out, the peace
follows logically after the ponoi. The goddess Aos, then, was the
citizens’ healer, as causal gar makes clear (just as Hegesichora will
provide the chorus of girls with peace). F. translates eks Hagesikhoras
(line 90) as “away from Hagesichora,” but the idea seems to be that the
youths are set upon the path of peace “thanks to” Hagesichora, just as
the city is set upon the path of peace thanks to Aos.
F. also suggests that the horse imagery in the poem refers to the
horse-driven celestial bodies of the night sky, and that the number ten in
the final stanza can be understood in reference to Pythagorean cosmology
and harmonics. This moves a long way from the opinio communis, which
interprets the ten simply as a reference to the number of individuals in
the chorus. Moreover, the horse imagery cannot obviously be connected with
astral imagery, nor is the number ten obviously connected with Pythagorean
cosmology in this text. In fact, the Greek geographic epithets associated
with the horses (Venetic, Colaxean, Ibenian) do not trigger associations
with stars but with places on earth, and the “ten of children” in
Alcman’s text makes perfect sense as a reference to the number of
performers.
In Chapter 3, “Ritual in Performance,” F. considers performance
context. Like most commentators, she assumes that the poem was part of a
state festival, and stresses that the festival “had the function of
linking the orderly workings of the cosmos to the well-ordered city” (p.
107). Since F. assumes that the poem preserves the dance of the Hyades, she
suggests that it was performed at the changing of seasons, and views the
performance as a rite of passage for the performers. F. elegantly discusses
the discourse of praise and blame inherent in the poem, as well as
noteworthy functions of dramatic technique, such as Alcman’s use of what
would later be known as the Brechtian Verfremdungstechnik. She also finds
within the poem a strong strain of lament, which she links to Spartan
society, In my opinion, the section on lament is inadequately supported.
In her postscript, F. suggests that Alcman’s poem was performed at the
Karneia festival, and looks at representations of the kalathiskos-dance,
which she interprets in relation to the dance of the stars hypothesized for
Alcman’s text. With regard to the Karneia, F. provides a revisionist
argument, suggesting that this is a winter rather than a summer festival.
F. works comfortably with philological, historical, art-historical and
anthropological data and methods, and has written an impressively
interdisciplinary book. But the passages in Alcman’s text that are
problematic for her thesis are too often passed by unmentioned or are
interpreted tendentiously: F. has not successfully supported her thesis.
CHRIS ECKERMAN
University of Oregon
You may remove yourself from the CJ-Online listserv by sending an email to:
[log in to unmask]
Leave the subject line blank, and in the first line of the message write:
UNSUBSCRIBE CJ-Online
If you have been forwarded this review, you may subscribe to the listserv
by sending an email to: [log in to unmask]
Leave the subject line blank, and in the first line of the message write:
SUBSCRIBE CJ-Online
|