Critical Moments in Classical Literature: Studies in the Ancient View of 
Literature and its Uses. By RICHARD HUNTER. Cambridge: Cambridge University 
Press, 2009. Pp. 217. Cloth, $95.00. ISBN: 978–0–521–51985–4.

Order this text for $92.63 from Amazon.com 
using this link and benefit CAMWS and the Classical Journal:

http://www.amazon.com/exec/obidos/redirect-home/classjourn-20

Previously published CJ Online reviews are at 
http://classicaljournal.org/reviews.php


CJ Online 2010.06.03

Richard Hunter (hereafter H.) begins his new book by telling us what it is 
not. It is not “the much-needed study of the mutual interchange between 
poetic imagery and ideas and the language of ancient criticism” (p. 8). 
Nor is it a history or a survey of literary criticism in antiquity. Rather, 
it is an endeavor to stitch together some surviving threads of the critical 
discussion of literature in antiquity. Because that discussion was recorded 
in snatches over centuries, and because only a small portion of that 
discussion is extant, the task of probing ancient critical views of 
literature makes the argument from silence attractive. Although H.’s 
essays verge on that fallacy at times, he never pushes the evidence so hard 
that it plunges off a precipice. Instead, his creative approach to 
problematic evidence offers refreshing insights into the ancient view of 
literature.

H.’s secondary aim is “to pay particular attention … to antiquity’s 
concern with what literature was for, what its ‘uses’ were” (p. 8). 
Indeed, he goes further and expresses his hope of making clear why a 
utilitarian view of literature and its criticism made sense in antiquity 
“and why it still should” (p. 8). This statement might cause some 
scholars to mutter accusations of philistinism, especially in times when 
the only acceptable defense of the study of literature seems to be an 
appeal to its intrinsic value. But H. wishes to show that the point of the 
discussion in antiquity was that “classical literature actually mattered; 
it was worth the continuing struggle to understand and exploit, even as 
intellectual and cultural contexts shifted” (p. 9). The essays that 
follow this bold statement demonstrate that the same is true today, and for 
the same reasons.

The first chapter, “Aristophanes Frogs and the critical tradition,” 
sets the stage, as it were, for the rest of the book, since Frogs surfaces 
as a point of reference in many of the following chapters. H. places 
Aristophanes’ comedy at the center of the tradition of criticism in 
antiquity by showing how the contest between Aeschylus and Euripides 
influenced and informed discussions about tradition and innovation for 
centuries. In particular, critics picked up the juxtaposition of 
Aeschylus’ archaic style and Euripides’ more contemporary approach, and 
they then began to extend the contrast beyond verse to modes of living. As 
H. puts it, “Frogs bequeathed to the critical tradition not just a way of 
talking about poetic style, but also a critical language which uses 
sociopolitical distinctions to describe levels of style” (p. 19). 
Aristophanes was hardly the first person, of course, to engage in 
comparative literature; but H. gives prominence to Frogs because it 
crystallizes the tension between old and new, correct and transgressive, 
traditional and innovative. With examples from Plato to Dio Chrysostom, H. 
argues persuasively for the enduring importance of the play for literary 
criticism. To buttress that point and impart some unity to his collection 
of essays, he grants Frogs at least a cameo appearance in almost every 
chapter of his book.

In the next chapter, “Readings of Homer: Euripides’ Cyclops,” H. 
examines the only complete surviving satyr play as “a very striking 
instance of how later writers appropriate, and often … literally 
‘re-write’ their predecessors by bringing out the ‘modern’ 
structures which can be found there” (p. 55). For example, when Silenos 
leads Odysseus to the highest point of Sicily (v.114), and Odysseus then 
asks him, “Where are the walls and the towers of a/the city?” the 
suggestion is that Odysseus knows Sicily not as Homer depicted it but as 
Euripides’ contemporaries knew it, as a populated and civilized island 
(p. 63). Through many other examples, H. shows how Euripides’ 
appropriation of a seminal episode from the Odyssey represents a critical 
reading of his predecessors and is thus an important witness to the ancient 
discussion of literature.

H. next turns his attention to the fragmentary “Comparison of 
Aristophanes and Menander,” a work that survives as part of Plutarch’s 
Moralia (853a–4d). In a chapter entitled “Comic moments,” H. examines 
the work’s views of the contrast between Old and New comedy. When 
Aristophanes pitted Aeschylus against Euripides, the elder playwright 
prevailed for many reasons, but mostly because he was not Euripides. That 
is, Euripides’ innovations and taste for realism offended the 
sensibilities of his audience, which was feeling conservative as it pined 
away for the “good old days” before the war. When it is Aristophanes’ 
turn to represent the Old (comedy, that is), the tables are turned, for 
Menander’s elevated and more respectable style carries the day. The 
judgment is harsh: Menander’s plays offer useful instruction, whereas 
“Aristophanes satisfies neither the many nor the intelligent. His poetry 
is like a retired prostitute who pretends to be a married woman” (p. 78). 
[[1]] In the rest of the chapter, H. pursues this line of criticism as it 
pertains to Roman comedy, noting especially the problem of Plautus, who was 
either a national treasure or a smudge on Rome’s literary heritage, 
depending on the point of view. The chapter concludes with an intriguing 
discussion of satire as a blend of Old Comic attack and New Comic 
instruction.

Chapter 4, “The ugly peasant and the naked virgins: Dionysius of 
Halicarnassus, On Imitation,” is the least successful in the book, for H. 
stretches too far in his attempt to reconstruct Dionysius of 
Halicarnassus’ fragmentary and corrupt work. His aim is “to trace, 
however faintly, the classical inheritance of Dionysius’ classicising 
theory” (p. 109). “Faintly” is a good word to use, since H. spins off 
his discussion in a number of different directions to cover the massive 
subject of mimesis in ancient literary criticism, all the while trying to 
reconstruct Dionysius of Halicarnassus’ contribution to the discussion. 
Some praise is due the creative attempts to tie all this together, but the 
chapter’s only success comes from demonstrating the frustrations and 
temptations that await anyone who works on a fragmentary text.

No book on ancient literary criticism would be complete without a section 
on “Longinus’” On the Sublime. Or is that really so? H. includes a 
lengthy discussion of the work in his fifth chapter, but it is not as 
challenging or illuminating as the other chapters. H. opens with a 
manufactured link to the Frogs that is obviously an attempt to stitch this 
essay into the collection. From there, he covers subjects already discussed 
in sufficient detail by “Longinus” himself, and he does little to 
promote On the Sublime as a critical moment in the history of literary 
criticism.

Much more interesting is the final chapter, “Reading for life: Plutarch, 
‘How the young man should study poetry.’” H. again begins with a 
manufactured link to the Frogs, but he quickly moves on to discuss 
Plutarch’s essay as an important work in its own right. Here H. 
accomplishes his goal of showing us why a utilitarian view of literature 
mattered in antiquity, and why it still should. Plutarch’s essay 
anticipates the argument most often used today in defense of education in 
the humanities, i.e., that reading allows students to practice critical 
thinking and judgment. However true that may be, too often those who use 
the argument are hard-pressed to provide examples to support their case, or 
even to demonstrate critical thinking to their students. Hunter, however, 
shows how Plutarch engages with previous criticism, particularly that of 
Plato, and how he arrives at a practical way of using literature to 
instruct the young: rather than being censored, poetry should be subject to 
guided, critical evaluation. In this way, students learn by observation how 
to think critically about anything that they will encounter in public life. 
That is, after all, the important point: the purpose of reading poetry, 
according to Plutarch, is not to prepare students to become scholars, but 
to equip them with the skills they will need to act intelligently in their 
public careers. Engagement with literary criticism will help them become 
critical thinkers in their own right.

H. appears to have taken a page from Plutarch’s essay, since he ends his 
book abruptly, with no conclusion or closing remarks. This is a surprise, 
given his attempts to create a sense of unity in the volume. However 
tenuous and artificial the connections between the individual chapters may 
be, they create the expectation that H. will sum up his observations 
somehow. Instead, he leaves us to reach our own conclusions. Plutarch would 
be proud, but H.’s readers may be disappointed.

SAMUEL J. HUSKEY
University of Oklahoma

[[1]] Hunter’s adaptation of D.A. Russell’s translation of Plutarch, 
Moralia 854a.


If you have been forwarded this review, you may subscribe to the listserv 
by sending an email to: [log in to unmask]
Leave the subject line blank, and in the first line of the message write: 
SUBSCRIBE CJ-Online

You may remove yourself from the CJ-Online listserv by sending an email to: 
[log in to unmask]
Leave the subject line blank, and in the first line of the message write: 
UNSUBSCRIBE CJ-Online